by Alan F. Alford
from
Eridu Website
Nearly twenty-four hundred years ago, the Athenian philosopher Plato
penned one of the most controversial and tantalizing stories ever
written. Once upon a time, he said, there had existed a magnificent
seafaring civilization which had attempted to take over the world,
but had perished when its island sank into the sea – the result of
an unbearable cataclysm of earthquakes and floods. This civilization
had been called Atlantis, and it had heralded from the Atlantic
Ocean, taking its name from the god Atlas who presided over the
depths of the sea. Its main island had sunk some nine thousand years
before the time of Solon, circa 9600 BC by our modern-day system of
reckoning.
The
puzzle of Atlantis is this. On the one hand, Plato was adamant that
the island had sunk in the Atlantic Ocean, and equally adamant that
the story was absolutely true. And yet, on the other hand, modern
scientists have mapped the floor of the Atlantic Ocean, using echo
sounders, ‘Geosat’ radar and multibeam sonar, and found no trace
whatsoever of any sunken island. The result is a deadlock on how to
decipher the story. Some argue that it is a myth, of uncertain
meaning. Others argue that it is a moral and political fable. And
others, still, continue to argue that it is pure history, and that
Plato simply got his geographical facts wrong.
In ‘The Atlantis Secret’ (click image right),
I suggest a new solution to this age-old mystery.
The essence of my theory is that the story of Atlantis – or strictly
speaking the story of the war between Ancient Athens and Atlantis –
was an allegory for the myth of the creation of the Universe. Or, in
other words, an encrypted account of a secret tradition which had
been preserved for millennia by the mystery schools of Egypt,
Mesopotamia, and Greece.
In this way, Plato’s story of Atlantis may be seen as a ‘true
story’. For the ancients sages believed that the myth of creation
was an absolutely true account of how the Universe had been brought
into being.
My theory has the rare distinction of being able to explain every
single aspect of Plato’s story, in contrast to historical
interpretations which are always forced to reject the legitimacy of
one or more crucial elements in the account. This does not guarantee
that the creation myth theory of Atlantis is correct, but it does
make it the only satisfactory theory currently available.
Support for my theory comes from Professor Christopher Gill, who is
one of the world’s leading experts on Plato and the Atlantis story.
In his Foreword to ‘The Atlantis Secret’, Gill writes:
“ Alan Alford’s book has the
considerable merit that, while offering a widely accessible
account of the Atlantis story, it strongly rejects the popular
view that the story has a historical basis. The book takes as
its starting point a fact often ignored in non-specialist
treatments of Atlantis: that Plato is the original and only
primary source for the story, and that we must begin by locating
the story within Plato’s philosophical and conceptual
world-view... I applaud the lucidity of Alford’s argument and
the transparency with which his claims are based on either
quoted or fully documented sources... I am very glad to have
encountered such a lucid and wide-ranging statement of this
[creation myth] hypothesis, and to see it applied so
suggestively to the Atlantis story.”
Before I summarize the merits of my new
approach to the Atlantis mystery, I will first address the
fundamental problems of the historicist theories.
I should preface the following remarks by reminding the reader that
the story of Atlantis is told only in the works of Plato,
specifically in the books ‘Timaeus’ and ‘Critias’, which he penned
during the 4th century BC. Many misconceptions have arisen from the
fact that people have not bothered to read or understand Plato,
preferring instead to lend credence to the opinions of later
commentators such as Ignatius Donnelly, Madame Blavatsky, and
Edgar
Cayce, who have consistently promoted the idea that the story of
Atlantis was a true in a historical sense. It is my sincere belief
that these modern individuals have muddied the waters of Plato’s
original account (no pun intended).
Problems
with the Popular Conception of Atlantis
Problem 1: Plato
As much as Atlantis-hunters would wish Plato to have been a
historian in the mould of Herodotus or Thucydides, he was not.
And nor was he a geographer in the mould of, say, Hecataeus. On
the contrary, Plato was a philosopher and a part-time
mythologist. Moreover, he was not even an ordinary philosopher;
rather, he was a ‘true philosopher’, whose interests lay
primarily in metaphysical, otherworldly matters. Therefore, if
there is any truth behind Plato’s account of Atlantis, it is
unlikely to have anything to do with history or geography;
rather, it should be rooted in myth, mysticism, esotericism and
the metaphysical world.
Problem 2:
Herodotus
It is highly significant that Herodotus, the so-called ‘father
of history’, said nothing at all about any war between Athens
and Atlantis. Writing almost a century before Plato, Herodotus
was widely travelled (he had visited Egypt where the Atlantis
story supposedly came from) and very knowledgeable about
military history. But as far as he was concerned, the greatest
wars of history had been those between Greeks and Persians,
notably the battle of Marathon (490 BC), the battles of
Thermopylae and Salamis (480 BC), and the battle of Plataea (479
BC). Moreover, in regard to the battle of Plataea, Herodotus
tells a highly revealing story of a bragging contest between the
Athenians and the Tegeans in which each side listed their
greatest military accomplishments. Here, the Athenians recited
their heroism at the battle of Marathon, but spoke also of their
achievements in ‘ancient times’ – their intervention in the war
of ‘the Seven against Thebes’, their repulsion of the Amazonians
who had invaded Attica, and their instrumental role in the
Trojan War. But as for the idea that their ancestors had
repulsed the invasion of Atlantis, the Athenian soldiers said
nothing at all – a very strange omission if Plato’s account
contained any historical truth.
Plato’s story is also called into question by several other
statements made by Herodotus. The greatest danger ever faced by
the Athenians, he said, was when the Persian army had invaded
Attica and instigated the battle of Marathon (490 BC). The
biggest armed force ever assembled, he said, was that of the
Persian king Xerxes (480 BC). The biggest island in the whole
world, he said, was Sardinia. And the earliest sea empire in the
Mediterranean, he said, had been forged by king Minos of
Knossos. All of these claims fly in the face of Plato’s claim,
nearly a century later, that Atlantis had been the biggest
island in the world and had assembled the largest army ever, to
forge the first sea empire of the Mediterranean.
Thus spoke the historian Herodotus who, had he lived a century
later, would have been highly skeptical of the historicity of
Plato’s story.
Problem 3:
Socrates
Socrates was one of the greatest intellectuals of his day, and
yet when Critias introduced the story of Athens’ heroic victory
over Atlantis, he responded by saying:
“Tell me though, what was
that ancient deed our city performed...? I’ve never heard of
it.”
If the Athenian victory had been magnificent in a
historical sense, or even in an orthodox mythical sense (as in
their involvement in the Trojan War or the earlier epic battle
‘the Seven against Thebes’), then Socrates certainly would have
heard of it. QED. We must be dealing here with a myth and,
moreover, with a new myth – perhaps a variation on a theme.
Problem 4:
The Saite Calendar
That a cataclysm could have instigated the beginning of a
calendar nine thousand years before the time of Solon (c. 9600
BC) is not implausible. Nor is it implausible that such a
calendar could have been preserved for nine thousand years and
handed down for posterity via the Egyptian Saites (compare the
Hebrew calendar which is today nearly six thousand years old).
It is therefore possible that Solon (or perhaps Plato himself)
learned the date of the Atlantis cataclysm from the Egyptian
priests at the town of Sais. But the important question is this:
is it really likely that the date of the cataclysm originated in
this way?
In fact, everything we know about ancient Egypt argues against
the possibility. Archaeologists have found no evidence at all
for a calendar of this ilk. Nor is there any such evidence in
the Egyptian texts, which generally refer to ancient events in
the vaguest of terms. Moreover, even when we do find numbers in
these texts, they usually turn out to be sacred, symbolic or
rounded, the latter suggesting some imaginative ex-post
rationalization by the priests. To presume, as some researchers
do, that the Saites possessed a calendar dating back nine
thousand years (to a time one thousand years earlier than the
foundation of their own state) is to go far beyond what can be
justified.
There is more. Why is it that the Saite tradition preserved only
the date of the Atlantis cataclysm? After all, Plato had the
Egyptian priest claim that several cataclysms had occurred after
the sinking of Atlantis, including the famous flood of Deucalion.
And yet nowhere in Egypt, nor in Plato, nor anywhere else in the
Greek writings, do we find any record of the dates of these
subsequent cataclysms. If Solon (or Plato) really did receive
the date of the Atlantis cataclysm from the Egyptian priests,
why did he not also receive the dates of the other, more recent
events?
There is another problem, too. Why is it that only the Egyptian
Saites preserved the date of the Atlantis cataclysm? If the
event was historical and as dramatic as Plato suggests, then it
would have affected much of the world and would have been
recorded in other ancient traditions. But, despite the
prevalence of worldwide flood myths, no record has ever been
found pointing to the date 9600 BC.
In summary, it is a leap of faith to suppose that the Egyptian
Saites had access to the purported date when no-one else in the
world did; it is a further leap of faith to suppose that the
Egyptian records were entirely destroyed (from an archaeological
perspective); it is a further leap of faith to suppose that
Solon had access to these records when no-one else did; and it
is a leap of faith, too, to suppose that Solon’s testimony fell
into the hands of Plato and no-one else. To go with all these
suppositions is to hop, skip and jump into the land of
improbability. And there still remains the awkward problem of
explaining how Plato (or the Egyptians, if one prefers) knew the
date of the Atlantis cataclysm but not the dates of the three,
more recent cataclysms that followed it, including the
well-known flood of Deucalion.
A more likely explanation for the date of the war is that Plato
was speaking idiomatically and that ‘nine thousand years ago’
signified ‘nine eons ago’, i.e. an infinitely long time ago. See
the evidence compiled in my book.
Problem 5:
Lost Civilizations
The implication of the historicist argument is that two highly
advanced civilizations – Atlantis and Athens respectively –
existed c. 9600 BC. And yet, according to archaeologists,
civilization began much more recently, c. 4000 BC (in the lands
of ancient Egypt and Mesopotamia). How, then, could the two
fantastic civilizations described by Plato have existed more
than five thousand years earlier, during what archaeologists
call ‘the Neolithic period’? The idea is controversial, to say
the least.
As regards Atlantis, Plato placed the former island in the
Atlantic Ocean. On this point, his language is unequivocal.
Atlantis had been in the great Ocean, in the Atlantis Ocean, in
the realm of Atlas, opposite the Pillars of Heracles (the
straits of Gibraltar) and, fully consistent with this, the Atlantians had directed their hostilities against Europe and
Asia. To look for Atlantis anywhere else but the Atlantic Ocean
is to totally ignore what Plato actually wrote. Unfortunately
for Atlantis-hunters, this leads to a fundamental problem,
namely that scientists have nowadays mapped the floor of the
Atlantic Ocean, in outline, using echo sounders, ‘Geosat’ radar
and multibeam sonar, without discovering any trace of the sunken
island or continent as described by Plato. The historicist
interpretation of Plato’s Atlantis is thus strongly contradicted
by scientific evidence.
Moreover, there is equally strong evidence against the idea of a
10th millennium BC civilization in Athens in Greece. The
earliest temples in Athens, for example, have been dated
archaeologically to only the 8th century BC; below their
foundations there is only virgin soil.
On the face of it, then, as we enter the
21st century AD, the notion of two highly advanced civilizations
fighting a worldwide war c. 9600 BC would seem to be a complete
fantasy.
Rather, the date of ‘nine thousand years ago’ is surely idiomatic
for ‘an infinitely long time ago’, as suggested earlier.
Moving
the Goal Posts
The reaction of Atlantis-hunters to the non-discovery of Atlantis on
the floor of the Atlantic Ocean has been to suggest that the story
was garbled at some point or else expressed in poetic terms, thus
causing Plato to cite an incorrect geography. This assumption means
that the lost island can be moved from the Atlantic to any other
alternative location, preferably one that has not been mapped by
sonar! The problem with this approach is that, once one presumes
Plato to have made one mistake (with the location), it becomes
tempting to take a little license with the text, and then some more
license still, and thus the situation arises where Atlantis-hunters
produce ‘solutions’ that owe little to what Plato actually said.
What we should be looking for is an island of circular shape, larger
than Libya and Asia Minor combined (!), fringed by mountains, with a
rectangular plain and a six-ringed, circular city within. But what
we get is the mountains alone, or the plain alone – and always of
the wrong dimensions – with the other features conveniently ignored.
At the extreme, some researchers have even staked their reputations
on islands that have not yet sunk. To which one must retort that if
an island isn’t sunk, then it isn't Plato’s Atlantis.
The
Creation Myth Theory
My theory rejects the historical interpretation of Plato’s story and
suggests instead that the Atlantis story – or rather the story of
the war between Ancient Athens and Atlantis – was ‘true’ in a
mythical sense in that it allegorized the creation of the Universe.
The validity of my theory stems from the ancient axiom that the myth
of creation was a true story.
The four keys to my theory are as follows:
-
Atlantis was a metaphor for the
primeval underworld (the interior of the earth).
-
The invasion of the known world
by Atlantis allegorized the eruption of the underworld.
(Note: this is a key aspect of the creation myth).
-
Ancient Athens, which
represented the ideal, or archetypal, city, first existed in
the sky in the form of a celestial body, i.e. a metaphorical
city. (Note: the lowering of cities from the heavens to the
Earth is a feature of Mesopotamian and Hindu mythology.)
-
The defeat of Atlantis by
Ancient Athens allegorized the fall of the sky and the war
between Heaven and Earth. (Note: this is another key aspect
of the creation myth, and parallels Hesiod’s tale of the
cataclysmic battle between the gods and the Titans.)
The Merits of
the Creation Myth Theory
-
The theory accords with the most
important facts of Plato’s story. By identifying Atlantis
with the underworld, it allows Atlantis to be in the
Atlantic Ocean (which symbolized the subterranean sea); it
allows Atlantis to be sunk; and it allows Atlantis to be
larger than two continents. These are fundamental points,
and yet all other Atlantis theories reject the legitimacy of
either one, two, or all three, of these statements and
suppose, instead, that Plato somehow, like an idiot, got
things cockeyed.
-
The theory decodes Atlantis in
the context of its invasion of the world and ensuing war
with ancient Athens. The worst thing a researcher can do is
to study either one of these cities in isolation from the
context of the war. My theory, however, makes the
inter-relationship between Athens and Atlantis a fundamental
basis of the interpretation.
-
The theory accounts for all of
the bizarre elements in Plato’s story. It explains how the
six-ringed city of Atlantis came out of Clito’s primeval
hill. It explains why the island was a perfect circle (code
for a sphere). It explains the unknown metal oreichalkos
(meteoritic iron). It explains how the island was
transformed into a shallow sea of mud. It explains why the
Athenian army sank suddenly into the Earth. And it even
explains the opposite continent which, bizarrely, was said
to completely surround the true Ocean.
-
The theory is able to resolve a
crucial perceived anomaly in Plato’s text. By proposing that
Athens descended from Heaven against Atlantis, it verifies
Plato’s statement that the war between the two sides
coincided with the foundation of Athens in the Earth ‘nine
thousand years ago’, and it thus exonerates Plato from the
accusation that he made a careless chronological error. The
supposed error, in fact, turns out to be a linchpin to
understanding the story.
-
The theory improves
substantially the reading of the story. By proposing that
the Athenian army descended from Heaven, it explains why the
warriors sank, all at once, beneath the earth. The
Athenians, far from suffering a tragic accident some time
after the war (as the badly mistranslated text suggests),
rather died a heroic death at the climactic moment of the
war. This, surely, was Plato’s intention, given that the
story was told, ostensibly, to depict Socrates’ ideal state
in action (“I’d love to see our city distinguish itself in
the way it goes to war and in the way it pursues the
war...”).
-
The theory vindicates Plato’s
claim that the story of the war was absolutely true. By
proposing that the story was a re-telling of the creation
myth (the war between Heaven and Earth variant), it allows
that the story be true in the mythical sense.
-
The theory takes into account
the wider aspects of Platonic philosophy. It must be
emphasized (no doubt to the great disappointment of many
Atlantis-hunters) that Plato was no historian or geographer,
and thus we are hardly likely to find an account of a lost
civilization at the heart of his works. On the contrary,
both Plato and Socrates were ‘true philosophers’, who were
obsessed with cosmogony and the theory of the soul. In their
way of thinking, something important had indeed been lost,
but it belonged to myth rather than to history, and to
Heaven rather than to Earth. Here, the Theory of Forms is
the key, for it presupposes a fall of the archetypes from
Heaven to Earth, including, most significantly, the
archetype of the ideal state, which was, after all, the
subject of Plato’s story. By proposing that Ancient Athens
(and earlier Atlantis) had fallen from Heaven to Earth (into
the underworld), my theory cuts to the very heart of
Platonic philosophy.
-
The theory sets Plato’s story of
Athens and Atlantis against the broader context of ancient
Greek myths, and the older Near Eastern myths from which the
Greek ones were largely derived. In these myths, important
parallels are found for ideas such as: the birth of the
Universe in a cataclysm; the fall of the sky; the fall of
the golden age; the wars of the gods of Heaven and the
underworld; the fall of gods, islands and continents from
Heaven into the underworld or subterranean sea; the birth of
all things from the Earth or subterranean sea (impregnated
by the seed of Heaven); and the idea that mythical peoples
dwelt in Heaven, the Earth and the underworld. Most
importantly, these creation myths enshrine the principle of
personification, with the poets using human-like gods or
heroes to personify the falling sky and the erupting
underworld. My interpretation of Plato’s story thus has its
roots in a well-documented, three-thousand-year-old literary
tradition.
Summary
In summary, I would remind the reader that there is no
archaeological evidence for the historicity of the war between
Athens and Atlantis (quite the opposite); that there is no evidence
whatsoever for a sunken island-continent on the Atlantic Ocean
floor; that Herodotus and Socrates had never heard of the
Athens-Atlantis war; that Plato did insist on the poetic (i.e.
mythical) nature of Solon’s story by comparing Solon to the great
poets Homer and Hesiod; that Plato did place the war in a pre-diluvian
era (predating the creation of mankind!); and that Plato was not a
historian, nor a geographer, but a true philosopher, whose interests
lay primarily in metaphysics, myths and mysticism.
It therefore makes sense that Atlantis signified the ‘true myth’ of
the creation of the Universe, encapsulating ideas such as the
antediluvian paradise lost, the fall of the sky, the mystery of the
underworld, and the mystery of the soul, or spirit, that had brought
everything to life.
Thus Atlantis becomes a symbol for a spiritual quest – the quest for
knowledge of the origins of the Universe, the quest for knowledge of
the origins of life, and the quest for knowledge of what life truly
is.
Alas! To search for Atlantis here on Earth, in the form of a lost
civilization, is the veritable antithesis of Plato’s philosophy. The
great man would be grieved indeed to witness such materialistic
folly.
|