November 17, 2017 from PreventDisease Website
Physicists have found it maddeningly difficult to write the observer out of quantum theory.
Now some are contemplating a mind-boggling alternative:
It looks like the "perspective of a madman", says the author of this bold new theory, because it compels us to abandon any notion of fundamental physical laws.
But if it stands up, it
would not only resolve some deep puzzles about
quantum mechanics, it
would turn our deepest preconceptions about reality itself inside
out.
This system extends this principle by stimulating our healing potential through the,
By giving direct instructions to our body’s intelligence, we stimulate its natural healing powers.
When it comes to forecasting how the world will behave, quantum theory is unsurpassed:
Electrons, for
instance, can sometimes
display behavior characteristic of waves,
even though they seem in other circumstances to behave like
particles.
Before observation, such quantum objects are said to be in a superposition of all possible observable outcomes.
This doesn't mean they exist in many states at once, rather that we can only say that all the allowed outcomes of measurement remain possible. This potential is represented in the quantum wave function, a mathematical expression that encodes all outcomes and their relative probabilities.
But it isn't at all obvious what, if anything, the wave function can tell you about the nature of a quantum system before we make a measurement.
That act reduces all those possible outcomes to one, dubbed the collapse of the wave function - but no one really knows what that means either. Some researchers think it might be a real physical process, like radioactive decay.
Those who subscribe to the many-worlds interpretation think it is an illusion conjured by a splitting of the universe into each of the possible outcomes.
Others still say that there is no point in trying to explain it - and besides, who cares? The maths works, so just shut up and calculate.
Whatever the case, wave function collapse seems to hinge on intervention or observation, throwing up some huge problems, not least about the role of consciousness in the whole process.
This is the measurement problem, arguably the biggest headache in quantum theory.
The most popular is known as the Copenhagen interpretation after the home city of one of quantum theory's pioneers, Niels Bohr.
He argued that quantum mechanics tells us only what we should expect when we make a measurement, not what causes that outcome. The theory can't tell us what a quantum system is like before we observe it; all we can ever ask of it is the probabilities of different possible outcomes.
Such a perspective seems to back you into an uncomfortable conclusion:
Can that be true? It seems the antithesis of what science normally assumes, as Einstein intimated.
Yet the idea has some pedigree.
Hungarian physicist John von Neumann was the first to entertain it in the early 1930s, and his compatriot Eugene Wigner went deepest with a thought experiment in the 1950s now known as Wigner's friend.
Suppose that Wigner is standing outside a windowless room where his friend is about to make some measurement on a particle.
Once that's done, she knows what the observed property of the particle is, but Wigner doesn't. He can't meaningfully say that the particle's wave function has collapsed until his friend tells him the result.
Worse still, until she does, quantum theory offers no way for Wigner to think about all the unseen events inside the lab as having fixed outcomes.
His friend, her measuring apparatus and the particle remain one big composite superposition.
It is as if we live in a solipsistic world where collapse only occurs when knowledge of the result impinges on a conscious mind.
John Wheeler at Princeton University put it differently:
We live, Wheeler said, in a "participatory universe" - one that can't be meaningfully described without invoking our active involvement.
But Wheeler could not escape the thicket of irresolvable questions that the participatory universe raises.
For one, Wigner and his friend seem locked in an infinite regress.
Despite the persistence of such questions, some theorists have recently returned to a form of Wheeler's vision, what Chris Fuchs at the University of Massachusetts in Boston has called "participatory reality".
That shift is partly for want of a better alternative, but primarily it is because if you take quantum mechanics seriously, some element of observer-dependent subjectivity seems impossible to avoid.
A couple of years ago, theorist Caslav Brukner at the University of Vienna revisited the Wigner's friend scenario in a slightly altered form proposed by David Deutsch at the University of Oxford.
Here the friend makes the measurement - she has collapsed the particle's wave function, producing either outcome A or B - but tells Wigner only that she sees a definite result, not what it is.
In Deutsch's scenario, Wigner is forced to conclude that his friend, her measuring apparatus and the particle are in a joint superposition, even though he knows a measurement has happened.
To Wigner's friend, she is definitely in, say, the state "I see A", but to Wigner she is in a superposition of "I see A" and "I see B".
So who's right? They both are, says Brukner, depending on whose point of view you adopt.
He has shown that if quantum mechanics is correct, there is no privileged perspective from which a third observer can reconcile both Wigner's and his friend's statements.
Rather, there are only facts for each observer.
One interpretation of quantum mechanics takes such a conclusion in its stride.
Devised in the 2000s by Fuchs and others, quantum Bayesianism (also known as QBism) is rooted in the view that quantum mechanics supplies only recommendations about what a rational observer should believe he or she will see on making a measurement - and that these beliefs can be updated as the observer takes fresh experiences into account.
That's where the "Bayesianism" comes in:
QBism point-blank denies that there is any objective notion of a quantum state at all.
This doesn't mean there can be nothing "real" beyond personal belief, only that quantum mechanics doesn't speak directly to that issue.
The existence of Brukner's "alternative facts" causes no pain in such a picture, because it has assumed them all along. Nor indeed does wave function collapse, which is then just a way of talking about how measurement updates our knowledge.
But few physicists are prepared to accept such stringent limits on their efforts to describe reality, which is why QBism remains a minority sport.
So what now? Enter Markus Muller, the self-described "madman" and a theorist at the University of Vienna.
His answer is to take things up a notch.
That means imagining that there are no fundamental laws of nature - no general relativity, no Maxwell's equations or Heisenberg's uncertainty principle - and asking what the world would then look like.
The answer might surprise you.
For even if you throw out physics, the logic of mathematics remains - and this is where Muller begins to construct his hypothetical world.
Let's say you have some experience X:
Given that, what are the chances you will then experience another outcome Y? There is a field of maths that deals precisely with such questions.
It's called algorithmic information theory and it shows how to make predictions based on inductive reasoning with a distinctly Bayesian flavor:
Muller wanted to see where that reasoning leads in a world with nothing else to shape it.
He represented each individual's experience at every instant as a string of bits of information - 1s and 0s, like binary computer code.
Each observer's history then consisted of a walk through the various possible bit strings, and the probability of going from one to the next would be random but conditional:
The idea, says theorist Giulio Chiribella at the University of Hong Kong,
You would think that such a picture could hardly be less likely to give rise to what we experience:
But when Muller used the methods of algorithmic information theory to figure out what sequences of bit strings are likely, he found something remarkable.
As these random experiences stack up, the conditional probability of the next experience, as described by a string of bits, tends to be higher for simpler bit sequences than for complex ones.
This makes it look as if there is a fairly simple algorithm generating the bit strings. So the observer deduces a simple "model" of reality, characterized by regular and comprehensible laws that smoothly connect one experience to the next.
This seems deeply odd:
It's a little like the way we understand a gas.
Although in principle all possible configurations of its molecules are allowed, the probability distribution of particle speeds we see has a simple bell-shaped curve, and the particles are distributed in space with bland uniformity.
Out of that come simple laws relating to things we can easily measure:
Those laws aren't written into the gas particles themselves; they are an emergent property of the probabilities of different configurations.
What's more,
That's because according to algorithmic information theory, the probabilities of bit strings for different observers will tend to converge on the same distribution - so they will agree on what the "laws of the world" are.
The surprises don't stop there.
This emergent reality should have just the qualities we see in quantum physics, where objects can show wave-like properties and behave in "non-local" ways, when a measurement on one particle can seem instantaneously to influence the state of another separated in space.
The upshot is that from the most minimal assumptions about the probabilities of what our personal experiences will contain, you can recover a world like the one we know.
It's not easy to see how Muller's ideas can be tested.
But circumstantial evidence that he could be on the right track comes with the way they solve the problem of Boltzmann brains, an almost metaphysical conundrum that suggests we are not the kind of beings we think we are.
All the same, this image of the universe built directly from observer experiences is so "out there" that other researchers barely know what to make of it.
It's,
Meanwhile, Brukner is keeping an open mind.
Muller himself is deeply aware that he has not chosen an easy path, but argues that it is one worth treading.
Conscious Collapse?
The idea that consciousness induces wave function collapse, the process by which myriad possible outcomes of a measurement become a single definite one, is not inherently absurd.
And yet physicists have long regarded it as a rather louche suggestion, because it seems to substitute one mystery for another:
Kelvin McQueen, a philosopher at Chapman University in California, and David Chalmers at the Australian National University in Canberra have recently started to make the case that we can now make things more precise.
The duo take their cue from integrated information theory, which posits that consciousness arises from interconnectivity in the brain.
Its inventor, neuroscientist Giulio Tononi at the University of Wisconsin-Madison, has even proposed a mathematical measure of consciousness, known as Phi, based on how the components of a system share and combine information.
Integrated information theory challenges the view that consciousness is all or nothing. It leaves open the possibility that non-human creatures, and maybe even simpler (for example, artificial) systems, can have some level of consciousness.
The idea has yet to be tested and no one has been able to formulate how Phi can be calculated for the human brain. But the prospect led McQueen and Chalmers to suggest a bold way of testing whether consciousness indeed causes wave function collapse.
In principle, McQueen says, you could do an ordinary quantum experiment with a twist:
If such particles had a large enough Phi, they might then automatically induce collapse and could not show the quantum effects, such as wave-like interference, that same-sized but lower-Phi particles would display.
McQueen is under no illusions about how hard it would be to set up such an experiment.
Cosmic Brains
In the late 19th century, Austrian physicist Ludwig Boltzmann described the world as space filled with particles in random motion, adopting all manner of different configurations.
Experiments have long confirmed that our reality matches this vision, but there's a problem.
If you examine the probabilities of each configuration, it turns out we are much less likely to be sentient beings who evolved on a planet over billions of years than ephemeral lone "brains", condensed out of chaos by sheer chance and floating freely, complete with imagined memories and experiences.
How can we know we aren't these "Boltzmann brains", apt to dissolve back into the fluctuating cosmos at any moment?
Physicists and philosophers have fretted over this for decades. But a radical new perspective can make the problem disappear.
If objective reality emerges from the mathematically predictable way our past experiences determine future observations, then sudden discontinuities in experience of the sort Boltzmann brains would encounter will be vanishingly improbable.
Experience should be smooth, connected and, at our scale, rather predictable.
Similar arguments make it unlikely that, as some researchers suggest, we are nothing more than "intelligent agents" in some super-intelligence's cosmic computer simulation.
That too would be vulnerable to abrupt events like shutdowns, whereas we have a persistent perception of reality.
|