by Sheila Jasanoff
and J. Benjamin Hurlbut
March
21, 2018
from
Nature Website
Illustration by Marina Muun
Sheila
Jasanoff and J. Benjamin Hurlbut
call for an
international network
of scholars and
organizations
to support a new
kind of conversation...
In August 2017,
scientists reported that they had
used the gene-editing tool
CRISPR-Cas9 to correct a mutation
in viable human embryos.
The work is just one of
countless applications of the technique, with which scientists hope
to alter plants, animals and humans.
The value of most applications of the technology has barely been
exposed to public review. Unless these editorial aspirations are
more inclusively debated, well-intentioned research could move
humanity closer to a future it has not assented to and might not
want.
Over the past three years, leading scientists have called for global
deliberation on the possible effects of gene editing on the human
future. 1
In our view, the
discussions that have taken place fall far short of the expansive,
cosmopolitan conversation that is needed.
Down from the
summit
An important milestone was the International Summit on Human Gene
Editing, held in Washington DC in December 2015. Organizers called
for an international forum to seek "broad societal consensus" on the
norms that should guide research. 2
Nobel laureate David Baltimore began the summit (below video) by invoking
the 1975
Asilomar meeting on recombinant DNA research: 3
"In 1975, as today,
we believed it was prudent to consider the implications of a
remarkable achievement in science. And then, as now, we
recognized we had a responsibility to include a broad community
in our discussions."
Asilomar is often remembered as a model of successful
self-regulation that affirmed science's autonomy and the principle
of responsible research.
Yet at the 2015 summit,
as
at Asilomar, the questions asked, the forms of expertise called
upon, and the definition of stakes for science and human life were
all shaped by those communities most aggressively advancing the
research.
The summit brought together a more diverse and international group
than is typical of meetings on the implications of scientific
research.
But the discussion still
focused on predictions about what genome editing will be able to do
in the near term and what its biological risks are, even though it
raises issues that clearly transcend immediate concerns for health
and safety.
Moreover, the meeting
format offered little opportunity for deeper listening or learning.
Instead, it encouraged an all-too-common pattern. 4
Discussion split into two
camps: scientific experts explored technical issues, whereas
scholars who study science and society addressed questions about the
possible disruption to social norms.
The two camps did not
inform each other.
To break out of this bifurcation between the 'science' and the
'ethics', methods must be found to get people to engage
substantively with each other. In our view, an entirely new type of
infrastructure is needed to promote a richer, more complex
conversation - one that does not originate from scientific research
agendas but that instead invites multiple viewpoints.
We advocate the establishment of a global observatory for gene
editing, as a crucial step to determining how the potential of
science can be better steered by the values and priorities of
society.
This would be an
international network of scholars and organizations similar to those
established for human rights and climate change.
The network would be
dedicated to gathering information from dispersed sources, bringing
to the fore perspectives that are often overlooked, and promoting
exchange across disciplinary and cultural divides.
Alternative
vision
In seeking new models, it is worth recalling a little-known meeting
held at Airlie House in Warrenton, Virginia in April 1976 - a
counterpoint to Asilomar's narrow, expert-dominated approach.
There, about 50
participants debated whether a new social contract was needed
between society and science. 5
Half of the group were
scientists; the rest were lawyers, public-interest advocates,
philosophers, journalists and congressional staff members.
At that gathering, the philosopher Stephen Toulmin declared
that science was facing the equivalent of the Protestant
Reformation that splintered Europe 500 years ago.
"People are tired of
being shut out of science's ecclesiastical courts and are
demanding to be let in," he said. Hans Jonas, another
philosopher, was more blunt.
"Scientific inquiry",
he said, "demands untrammeled freedom for itself." 6
Today, a reformation of
the contract between science and society is even more overdue, but
the institutional barriers are even more entrenched.
Certainly in relation to
gene editing, there has been much more advice from experts than
acknowledgement of the limits of such expertise.
In April 2017, we gathered three dozen,
...at Harvard University in
Cambridge, Massachusetts.
We discussed
how to
enable a different kind of conversation about the variety of
techniques with which scientists can edit living systems.
We did not start with the usual question of what science is ready to
achieve. Instead, we took a step back and asked to what extent
existing scientific and political institutions are capable of
initiating the forms of deliberation demanded by the prospect of
editing life.
We explored the rights
and responsibilities of scientific experts, policymakers, publics
and scholars in such processes.
And we asked what is
needed - in terms of representation and deliberation - for a
genuinely broad societal consensus on gene editing.
We agreed on the need for a coordinated international effort to
gather and analyze salient information on what is already being done
to integrate perspectives from science and society.
That effort would bring
to light divergent ideas about what is at stake in protecting the
integrity of life, human and non-human, against unwarranted
intrusion from new and emerging technologies.
We identified the need for a forum to promote sustained
international, interdisciplinary and cosmopolitan reflection on
several key considerations:
what questions should
be asked, whose views must be heard, what imbalances of power
should be made visible, and what diversity of views exist
globally.
We agreed that more
crosstalk is needed between people representing,
-
different
disciplines
-
political cultures
-
normative frameworks,
...so that
approaches currently taken for granted can be tested and
recalibrated in the light of alternative and dissenting
perspectives.
A new global forum,
grounded in a commitment to hospitality and friendship towards
unfamiliar, possibly upsetting ways of thought, would encourage
people to build a rapport and so begin to engage more meaningfully
with one another.
The International Summit on Human Gene Editing
was held in Washington DC in 2015.
Credit: Sam Risdon/The National Academies
To these ends, the global observatory we imagine would fulfill three
functions.
-
First, it would
serve as a clearing house.
It would consolidate and make
universally accessible the global range of ethical and
policy responses to genome editing and related technologies.
These responses
would include relevant literature, and position statements
from civil-society groups, especially from the global south.
The network would
also report on activities and outputs of formal bioethics
bodies, such as the Nuffield Council on Bioethics in the
United Kingdom or the German Ethics Council, professional
societies such as the American Society for Reproductive
Medicine, and intergovernmental agencies, such as the
Council of Europe and the World Health Organization.
-
Second, the
observatory would enable the tracking and analysis of
significant conceptual developments, tensions and emerging
areas of consensus around gene editing.
It would broaden
the focus beyond the technical pros and cons of gene editing
to a richer range of questions and concerns that tend to be
overlooked.
Studies of the social dynamics of international
collaborations - from setting research agendas to the
allocation of intellectual-property rights - could help to
reveal the hidden power imbalances in science that are
likely to influence who benefits from gene-editing research,
as well as who does not.
Likewise, the
material gathered in the global observatory would give us a
more detailed view of the biological futures people actually
want for themselves and their societies.
For instance, it
could shed light on differing perceptions of social and
biological relationships, such as ideas of disability and
disease, across cultures.
-
Third, the
observatory would serve as a vehicle for convening periodic
meetings, and seeding international discussion informed by
insights drawn from data collection and analysis.
To be effective in all
three dimensions identified, those involved must reject the rhetoric
of a competitive race in international science.
The fixation on 'winning'
should be replaced with deeper reflection on the purposes of
technological change. 7
Analysis of the contexts
in which the narrative of winners and losers emerges should itself
be part of the work of the observatory, as should its effects on the
course of scientific research.
Reframing the
questions
If successful, the observatory we propose would alter the way
problems are framed and expand the idea of a "broad societal
consensus".
In current bioethical debates, there is a tendency to fall back on
the framings that those at the frontiers of research find most
straightforward and digestible. This move comes at great cost.
If the ethical stakes of
human germline genome editing are limited to questions of physical
safety, for example, then the technical evaluation of particular
biological endpoints (for instance, off-target effects) might offer
sufficient answers. 8
But such a focus
short-circuits the central question of how to care for and value
human life, individually, societally and in relation to other forms
of life on Earth.
Likewise, the goals of consensus must go beyond merely agreeing on
whether particular applications of genome editing are acceptable or
unacceptable. Deliberation is insufficient if the conversation is
too quickly boxed into judgments of the pros and cons, risks and
benefits, the permissibility or impermissibility of germline genome
editing, and so on.
Such an approach neglects important background questions - who sits
at the table, what questions and concerns are sidelined, and what
power asymmetries are shaping the terms of debate.
When it comes to shaping
the future of humanity, those neglected issues are just as important
as the concerns of people poised to radically remake it. Indeed,
consensus might even mean agreeing not to proceed with some research
until a more equitable approach to setting the terms of debate is
achieved. 9
Cosmopolitanism, in styles of thought and in cultural intelligence,
is not merely an aspiration for the proposed observatory; it should
be integral to the network's way of working.
Success will ultimately
depend on whether those leading the initiative have the skill and
sensitivity to manage cross-disciplinary and cross-cultural
conversations, and are backed by the knowledge and networks needed
to sustain an infrastructure that facilitates these conversations.
Looking ahead
The observatory would not seek to engage in a race against science.
Its purpose is more to
engender robust, sustained conversation about the limits and
directions of research. The pace of current research might well
bring about some near-term interventions that humanity has not
consented to, such as the creation of an edited child.
Far from rendering
international deliberation moot, such a step would only underscore
the need for meaningful cosmopolitan thinking.
Our hope is that the observatory would begin to shift entrenched
habits of thought beyond those directly influencing gene-editing
research. Indeed, because the issues that the observatory would
illuminate reach far beyond narrow questions about particular
technologies and associated risks and benefits, its work should
enrich and deepen debate around biotechnology more broadly.
All too often, scientists and others have tended to circumscribe
debate about human genetic engineering on the premise that, until
the technical capability does exist, it is not necessary to address
difficult questions about whether such interventions in human life
are desirable. 10
For example, even as
scientists are applying
gene editing to human embryos in the lab,
the argument that the technology is too risky for clinical use
serves as an excuse to delay the hard work of thinking through the
technology's wider ramifications.
These tendencies to delimit and delay debate leave exploratory
research largely unquestioned. The effect is that scientific
developments, once they are realized, seem to have been inevitable
and outside our control, even though they are the products of
scientists' choices.
Questions of value then
seem largely reactive, even futile.
Thus, a big challenge will be to ensure that entry cards to the
observatory are not dictated by dominant cultural views about what
constitutes relevant moral or technical competence.
Profound and
long-standing 'traditions of moral reflection risk' being excluded
when they do not conform to Western ideas of academic bioethics.
But as the
Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change discovered through its
climate assessment exercises, formal scientific training cannot be
the only criterion by which to decide whose voices should be heard
in an inclusive global forum.
Equally, care must be
taken to ensure that participation is not preferentially given to
those who are the most vocal or most polarized on the issues.
Free enquiry, the lifeblood of science, does not mean untrammeled
freedom to do anything.
Society's unwritten
contract with science guarantees scientific autonomy in exchange for
a research enterprise that is in the service of, and calibrated to,
society's diverse conceptions of the good.
As the dark histories
of
eugenics and abusive research on human subjects remind us, it is at
our peril that we leave the human future to be adjudicated in
biotechnology's own "ecclesiastical courts".
It is time to invite in voices and concerns that are currently
inaudible to those in centers of biological innovation, and to draw
on the full richness of humanity's moral imagination.
An international,
interdisciplinary observatory would be an important step in this
direction.
References
-
Baltimore, D. et
al. Science 348, 36–38 (2015) -
A prudent path forward for genomic
engineering and germline gene modification
-
National
Academies of Sciences, Engineering, and Medicine. On Human
Gene Editing: International Summit Statement (Organizing
Committee for the International Summit on Human Gene
Editing, 2015).
-
Jasanoff, S.,
Hurlbut, J. B. & Saha, K. Issues Sci. Technol. Fall, 25–32
(2015) -
CRISPR democracy: Gene editing and the
need for inclusive deliberation
-
Snead, O. C. UC
Davis Law Rev. 43, 1529–1604 (2009) -
Science, public bioethics, and the
problem of integration
-
Steinfels, P.
Hastings Center Report 6(3), 21–25 (1976) -
Biomedical Research and the Public: A
Report from the Airlie House Conference
-
Culliton, B. J.
Science 192, 451–453 (1976) -
Public participation in science: still
in need of definition
-
Baylis, F. Nature
Hum. Behav. 1, 0103 (2017) -
Human germline genome editing and
broad societal consensus
-
National
Academies of Sciences, Engineering and Medicine - Human
Genome Editing: Science, Ethics, and Governance (National
Academies Press, 2017)
-
Jasanoff, S. -
The Ethics of Invention: Technology and the Human Future
(Norton, 2016)
-
Hurlbut, J. B. -
Experiments in Democracy: Human Embryo Research and the
Politics of Bioethics (Columbia Univ. Press, 2017)
|